How Long Will the Blackpill Last?
An article by Otieno Arudo .
How Long Will the Blackpill Last?
An article by Otieno Arudo .
"Nothing is indeed new under the sun", it was said by sages, and so perhaps thinkers may confidently claim that nothing has not yet been philosophized. This adage holds particular resonance when examining the emergence of the black pill movement within contemporary discourse. The black pill philosophy (a term herewith used loosely), which has gained traction in the digital age, among communities feeling disenfranchised in romantic and social spheres, echoes historical movements, particularly the 19th-century physiognomy movement. This school of thought posited that one's inner character and destiny could be deduced from physical appearance, a deterministic position much like that of the black pill which suggests an immutable fate based on traits like genetics and social status. This article embarks on a philosophical investigation to draw parallels between these two seemingly disparate ideologies, contextualizing their philosophies within the broader framework of human understanding and belief systems. We will explore how thinkers like Fichte and Nietzsche addressed the deterministic nature of physiognomy, and assess how these thoughts might apply or differ when addressing the black pill. Furthermore, this piece will delve into current debates surrounding the black pill, examining arguments from both advocates and detractors, to evaluate its potential cultural and political impact in shaping future societal norms and policies.
The main proponents of the physiognomy and phrenology movements, Johann Kaspar Lavater and Franz Joseph Gall, respectively, were influential figures in 18th and 19th-century Europe. Johann Kaspar Lavater, a Swiss poet, philosopher, and theologian born in 1741 in Zurich, was best known for his seminal work, "Physiognomische Fragmente zur Beförderung der Menschenkenntniß und Menschenliebe" (1775-1778). It proposed that one could discern an individual's moral character, intellect, and destiny by analyzing their facial features and body structure. His ideas gained significant popularity during a time when Enlightenment thought was questioning traditional views, yet his work paradoxically supported existing social hierarchies by suggesting a natural order based on physical appearance. Lavater's views had political implications, aligning with conservative elements
Franz Joseph Gall, born in 1758 in Tiefenbronn, Baden (now part of Germany), but who spent much of his career in Vienna, Austria, took these ideas further with the development of phrenology. As a neuroanatomist and physician, Gall posited that the brain was composed of distinct areas responsible for various mental faculties, and these could be discerned from the shape and bumps on one's skull. His work popularized phrenology, which extended physiognomy's principles by offering a pseudo-scientific basis for assessing character and intelligence. It should be mentioned that Gall's publishing coincided with renewed European nationalism and the aftermath of the French Revolution, which provoked intense debates about human nature . Phrenology, like physiognomy, was used to justify racial and social hierarchies, often supporting colonialist and eugenic policies. While Gall's ideas were initially met with enthusiasm, especially among those looking for scientific validation of social structures, they were also met with skepticism and eventually scientific refutation as the understanding of human biology advanced. Both movements, despite their eventual decline, had a lasting impact on how society viewed the link between physical traits and moral or intellectual worth.
And now let us delve into how various philosophers directly confronted the physiognomy movement, starting with Johann Gottlieb Fichte, a pivotal figure in German Idealism. Born in 1762, Fichte was a philosopher whose ideas revolved around the activity of the self and human freedom. Central to his philosophy is the concept of the self-positing "I" (Ich), where he argues that the self is not merely a passive entity shaped by external forces but actively constructs its identity through moral actions and decisions. This perspective directly opposes the physiognomic doctrine that one's character is predetermined by physical attributes. Fichte critiqued physiognomy for its deterministic approach, arguing that it reduces humans to mere manifestations of their physicality, stripping them of moral autonomy. Imagine, for instance, if one who was told their worth is judged based by the shape of their nose or the structure of their jaw,would they not be motivated to behave in a manner to disapprove the outcome burdened on them? Fichte insisted that true character is revealed through one's adherence to moral laws, though self-imposed. In works such as "The Vocation of Man" and "The Science of Knowledge," he underscores that moral conduct, driven by rational choice, is what defines us, not the static traits of our physical form.
Fichte's critique of physiognomy echoes his broader disdain for materialism, where he sees physiognomy as an overemphasis on the material at the expense of the spiritual and moral dimensions of humanity. His philosophy seeks to transcend the material world, advocating for a moral and intellectual elevation through self-realization. This stance is particularly evident in his advocacy for educational reform, where he believed that education could empower individuals to shape their own destinies, countering the fatalistic nature implied by physiognomy. In his political philosophy, notably in "Addresses to the German Nation," Fichte envisions a society where individuals are not categorized or judged by their physical appearances but are developed into autonomous beings through education and moral cultivation. This line of thought was influential, paving the way for philosophers like Hegel, who would further explore these ideas in his own dialectical method, emphasizing the dynamic evolution of the human spirit rather than its static physical representation.
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (another giant of German Idealism) philosophical system was profoundly influenced by thinkers like Kant and Spinoza, though neither directly addressed physiognomy. Hegel's masterpiece, "Phenomenology of Spirit," explores the development of consciousness towards Absolute Spirit, where he critiques the reductionist approaches akin to physiognomy by building upon Fichte's critique. In fact, German Idealism, as a philosophical movement, fundamentally opposes such pseudo-sciences by focusing on the role of the mind or spirit in understanding reality, rather than reducing human essence to physical attributes. Hegel, in particular, would argue against the over-reliance on empiricism, which he associated with the lower forms of consciousness like sense-certainty and perception. Physiognomy, with its claim to deduce character from physical features, exemplifies this empirical fallacy, for Hegel, because it does not engage with the dialectical progression of human consciousness or the rational spirit.
In Hegel's view, the development of collective consciousness into Spirit involves a journey through contradiction and synthesis, not static physical traits. Physiognomy, therefore, not only misunderstands the dynamic nature of human identity but also undermines the ethical and social dimensions of human life. Hegel's philosophy insists that freedom and morality are realized through rational activity and social institutions, as detailed in his "Philosophy of Right," where personal and societal development transcends mere biology. The physiognomic approach, by suggesting that character is fixed by appearance, would be detrimental to Hegel's conception of Spirit, which sees human beings as participants in a historical and cultural evolution where ethical life, art, and philosophy play crucial roles. Moreover, in his aesthetics, Hegel discusses beauty and art as expressions of spirit, not merely physical forms, further highlighting how physiognomy's focus on the corporeal misses the deeper spiritual truths. Thus, Hegel's critique of physiognomy is woven into his broader dialectical understanding of reality, where the development of consciousness towards freedom and ethical life stands in stark contrast to the static, deterministic views promoted by such pseudo-sciences.
Now we shall consider two other German greats in this discussion even though their writings do not directly address physiognomy Arthur Schopenhauer and Friedrich Nietzsche both have deterministic notes in their philosophical tunes contrasting with teachings that may also be interpreted in the opposite way enriching their respective concertos. Arthur Schopenhauer’s philosophy revolves around the concept of the "Will," an irrational, blind force driving all phenomena. On one hand, Schopenhauer's emphasis on the will as the source of all character could be seen as aligning with physiognomy's claim that one's nature is predetermined; he posits that character is largely innate, expressed through the body, which might suggest a connection between physical appearance and inner disposition. However, on further introspection, some of his other ideas castigate physiognomy for its superficiality and optimism about human nature. Schopenhauer's pessimism, where life is seen as suffering due to unquenchable desires, undermines the hopeful determinism (even if not for everyone) of physiognomy, which often supported social hierarchies. The philosophy of The World as Will and Representation author does not aim at societal reform like Hegel but rather at personal transcendence through compassion or asceticism, highlighting a disconnect between the physical and the moral self that physiognomy overlooks.
Friedrich Nietzsche, born in 1844 in Röcken, Prussia, offers a complex perspective influenced by both Spinoza and Hegel, yet his philosophy diverges significantly in its implications. Nietzsche's concept of the "will to power" can be seen as a rephrasing of Spinoza's monism and Hegel's spirit, where all life is an expression of a singular force or drive. His philosophy, especially in works like "Thus Spoke Zarathustra," might be read as supporting a deterministic view of character, akin to physiognomy, where one's "type" or "nature" dictates much of their life's path. However, this interpretation requires careful reading; Nietzsche's call for individuals to become "Übermenschen" (Overmen) suggests self-overcoming and the creation of one's values, opposing any static, physiognomic judgment. His critique of traditional morality and emphasis on personal transformation through the affirmation of life could be seen as an antidote to the deterministic pessimism of physiognomy.
The philosophies of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche fit more seamlessly into the modern black pill movement than into the physiognomy movement due to their emphasis on a pessimistic worldview and personal determinism. Both philosophers, with their focus on the will or will to power, suggest that life's outcomes are largely preordained by internal forces, resonating with the black pill's narrative of inescapable personal fates based on genetics, social status, or inherent characteristics. Unlike the physiognomy movement, which sought to justify social hierarchies through physical traits, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche's philosophies do not aim at supporting societal structures but rather critique them through their pessimism or call for self-legislation. Their ideas of individual suffering, the necessity of personal struggle against one's nature, and the creation of one's values provide a philosophical backbone for the black pill's emphasis on personal disenfranchisement and the rejection of traditional success narratives. This sets the stage for a deeper comparison between these historical philosophies and contemporary movements, highlighting how ideas of determinism, pessimism, and the will's expression have evolved from physical to existential determinism.
The black pill movement, a term first popularized in the 2010s on the incel-related blog "Omega Virgin Revolt," draws its name from the metaphorical use of "pills" inspired by the Matrix trilogy. In this series, protagonist Neo faces a choice between taking a blue pill to remain in blissful ignorance or a red pill to awaken to the harsh realities of the world. This metaphor has since dominated internet discourse, evolving into various "pills" representing different ideological awakenings or truths. The black pill specifically refers to a fatalistic worldview where one accepts the futility of changing their social, romantic, or sexual circumstances, believing these are predetermined by genetics, looks, or societal structures. This nihilistic perspective has resonated within online communities, particularly among those identifying as "incels" (involuntary celibates), where it signifies the belief that there's no escape from one's predestined fate, often leading to a rejection of traditional self-improvement narratives. Both the black pill and the physiognomy/phrenology movements share a deterministic belief system: physiognomy posited that one's character, intelligence, and destiny could be read from physical attributes, while the black pill asserts similar deterministic views based on genetics, appearance, or social status. Both philosophies have been used to justify social hierarchies, albeit in different contexts; physiognomy supported racial and class superiority, often aligning with conservative political actions aimed at maintaining the status quo. Conversely, the black pill, despite potentially perpetuating racist dynamics by suggesting, for instance, that certain racial groups are inherently more attractive, has a surprisingly racially diverse following. This phenomenon reflects a broader cultural shift towards what has been termed "post-ironic, post-racial fascism," where figures like Candace Owens and Nick Fuentes gain traction by advocating for right-wing ideologies while themselves being from minority backgrounds. This paradoxical adoption suggests a nuanced interaction with identity politics, where traditional racial boundaries are blurred in the service of ideological alignment, showing how the black pill movement navigates modern cultural landscapes in ways that echo the complexity of contemporary political discourse.
The current philosophical discourse around the black pill movement reveals a complex landscape of thought. Proponents or at least those whose philosophies resonate with aspects of the black pill, like Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, delve into the darker, more deterministic aspects of human nature, exploring themes of suffering, will, and power. These ideas have been adapted in the internet age to support the black pill's narrative, often through the lens of psychological and sociological data, which, however, is frequently criticized for its selective use or misinterpretation. On the other side of the debate, philosophers like Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus, rooted in existentialism, argue for human freedom and the capacity to impose meaning on an otherwise indifferent or absurd world. Their thoughts challenge the black pill's fatalism by emphasizing that individuals are not bound by their circumstances but can choose their path, even if it involves creating purpose in a seemingly purposeless universe. Additionally, contemporary critical theorists such as Judith Butler offer critiques centered on the social construction of identity and the performative aspects of human behavior, directly opposing the deterministic views by highlighting how identity is shaped by multiple (fluid) intersecting factors like race, gender, and class. This intersectional approach seeks to dismantle the black pill's rigid determinism by showcasing how social dynamics and individual agency interweave, offering a more hopeful, albeit complex, narrative about human possibility and societal change.
The physiognomy and phrenology movements, once influential, waned as their foundational claims were debunked by scientific advancements and philosophical critiques. Physiognomy's reliance on a now-disproven correlation between physical appearance and character traits was undermined by the development of psychology and anthropology, which demonstrated the complexity of human behavior and identity beyond mere physical attributes. Logical fallacies, such as confirmation bias and the naturalistic fallacy, where what is natural was assumed to be moral or right, were pivotal in their decline. Similarly, the black pill movement, with its deterministic views, faces an analogous fate as it grapples with the same issues of oversimplification and empirical invalidation. The movement's reliance on anecdotal evidence and selective data to support its claims mirrors the fallacies that physiognomy fell prey to, suggesting that as society's understanding of human behavior and social dynamics matures, the black pill's influence might also diminish.
However, the contemporary context introduces significant variables not present during the decline of physiognomy. The internet serves as a potent tool for radicalization, providing a platform where the black pill ideology can thrive through echo chambers that reinforce beliefs. Social media algorithms reward the unique and controversial voices of the black pill, amplifying their reach far beyond what was possible in the past. Coupled with a political climate that benefits from division, where leaders exploit cultural fractures for gain, and a legacy media landscape forced to navigate this new reality by pandering to various subcultures, the black pill movement finds fertile ground for longevity. Moreover, the global connectivity of subcultures, now celebrated or at least given airtime in the 24-hour news cycle, adds a layer of resilience to these ideologies. Issues like declining birth rates provide a fertile ground for the black pill to offer its interpretations, often based on skewed statistics, in a world where solutions to complex sociological problems require compromises that many are unwilling to accept. Given these factors, predicting the lifespan of the black pill movement is challenging; it might either fade as enlightenment spreads or persist, fueled by the very mechanisms of modern communication and politics.
The End.